Carneades

Carneades

Infobox Philosopher
region = Western Philosophy
era = Ancient philosophy
color = #B0C4DE



image_caption = Carneades, Roman copy after the sit statue exhibited on the agora of Athens, ca. 150 BC, Glyptothek
name = Carneades
birth = ca. 214 BC, Cyrene
death = ca. 129 BC
school_tradition = Academic Skepticism, Platonism
main_interests = Epistemology, Ethics
notable_ideas = Philosophical skepticism and a probabilistic account of knowledge
influences = Plato, Arcesilaus, Diogenes of Babylon
influenced = Clitomachus, Philo of Larissa, Sextus Empiricus

Carneades ( _el. Καρνεάδης) (c. 214129 BC) was a radical skeptic born in Cyrene and the first of the philosophers to pronounce the failure of metaphysicians who endeavored to discover rational meanings in religious beliefs. By the time of 159 BC he had started to refute all previous dogmatic doctrines, especially Stoicism, and even the Epicureans whom previous skeptics had spared. As head of the Academy, he was one of three philosophers sent to Rome in 155 BC where his lectures on the uncertainty of justice caused consternation among the leading politicians. He left no writings and many of his opinions are known only via his successor Clitomachus. He seems to have doubted the ability, not just of the senses but of reason too, in acquiring truth. His skepticism was, however, moderated by the belief that we can, nevertheless, ascertain probabilities of truth, to enable us to live and act correctly.

Life

Carneades, the son of Epicomus or Philocomiis, was born at Cyrene about the year 214 BC. He went early to Athens, and attended the lectures of the Stoics, and learnt there logic from Diogenes. He studied the works of Chrysippus, and exerted his energy of a very acute and original mind in their refutation.

He attached himself to the Academy, which had suffered from the attacks of the Stoics; and on the death of Hegesinus, he was chosen to preside at the meetings of Academy, and was the fourth in succession from Arcesilaus. His great eloquence and skill in argument revived the glories of his school; and, defending himself in the negative vacancy of asserting nothing (not even that nothing can be asserted), carried on a vigorous war against every position that had been maintained by other sects.

In the year 155 BC, when he was fifty-eight years old, he was chosen with Diogenes the Stoic and Critolaus the Peripatetic to go as ambassador to Rome to deprecate the fine of 500 talents which had been imposed on the Athenians for the destruction of Oropus. During his stay at Rome, he attracted great notice from his eloquent speeches on philosophical subjects, and it was here that, in the presence of Cato the Elder, he delivered his famous orations on Justice. The first oration was in commendation of the virtue of Roman justice, and the next day the second was delivered, in which all the arguments he'd made on the first were refuted, as he persuasively attempted to prove that justice was inevitably problematic, and not a given when it came to virtue, but merely a compact device deemed necessary for the maintenance of a well ordered society. Recognizing the potential danger of the argument, Cato was shocked at this and he moved the Senate to send the philosopher home to his school, and prevent the Roman youth from the threat of re-examining all Roman doctrines. Carneades lived twenty-seven years after this at Athens.

Carneades was succeeded, in his old age, by his namesake Carneades, son of Polemarchus, but the younger Carneades died c. 131 BC and was succeeded by Crates of Tarsus. [Algra, K., "The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy By Keimpe Algra," page 33.] The elder Carneades died at the advanced age of 85, or (according to Cicero) 90, in 129 BC. At this point Clitomachus became head of the Academy.

Carneades is described as a man of unwearied industry. He was so engrossed in his studies, that he let his hair and nails grow to an immoderate length, and was so absent at his own table (for he would never dine out), that his servant and concubine, Melissa, was constantly obliged to feed him. In his old age, he suffered from cataract in his eyes, which he bore with great impatience, and was so little resigned to the decay of nature, that he used to ask angrily, if this was the way in which nature undid what she had done, and sometimes expressed a wish to poison himself.

Philosophy

Carneades is known as an Academic Skeptic. Academic Skeptics (so called because this was the type of Skepticism taught in Plato's Academy in Athens) hold that all knowledge is impossible, except for the knowledge that all other knowledge is impossible.

Carneades left no writings, and all that is known of his lectures is derived from his intimate friend and pupil, Clitomachus; but so true was he to his own principles of withholding assent, that Clitomachus confesses he never could ascertain what his master really thought on any subject. He, however, appears to have defended atheism, and consistently enough to have denied that the world was the result of anything but chance. In ethics, which more particularly were the subject of his long and laborious study, he seems to have denied the conformity of the moral ideas with nature. This he particularly insisted on in the second oration on Justice, in which he manifestly wished to convey his own notions on the subject; and he there maintains that ideas of justice are not derived from nature, but that they are purely artificial for purposes of expediency.

All this, however, was nothing but the special application of his general theory, that people did not possess, and never could possess, any criterion of truth.

Carneades argued that, if there were a criterion, it must exist either in reason ("logos"), or sensation ("aisthêsis"), or conception ("phantasia"). But then reason itself depends on conception, and this again on sensation; and we have no means of judging whether our sensations are true or false, whether they correspond to the objects that produce them, or carry wrong impressions to the mind, producing false conceptions and ideas, and leading reason also into error. Therefore sensation, conception, and reason, are alike disqualified for being the criterion of truth.

But after all, people must live and act, and must have some rule of practical life; therefore, although it is impossible to pronounce anything as absolutely true, we may yet establish probabilities of various degrees. For, although we cannot say that any given conception or sensation is in itself true, yet some sensations appear to us more true than others, and we must be guided by that which seems the most true. Again, sensations are not single, but generally combined with others, which either confirm or contradict them; and the greater this combination the greater is the probability of that being true which the rest combine to confirm; and the case in which the greatest number of conceptions, each in themselves apparently most true, should combine to affirm that which also in itself appears most true, would present to Carneades the highest probability, and his nearest approach to truth.

References

ee also

*Anti-realism
*Moral relativism
*Plank of Carneades
*Philosophical skepticism
*Pyrrhonism
*Subjectivism

ources

*SmithDGRBM

External links

*sep entry|carneades|Carneades|James Allen
*iep|c/carneade.htm


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно решить контрольную?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Carnéades — Saltar a navegación, búsqueda Carnéades Carnéades, copia romana de la estatua sentada exhibida en el Ágora de Atenas, ca. 150 a. C., Gliptoteca de Múnich …   Wikipedia Español

  • Carneades — /kahr nee euh deez /, n. 214? 129? B.C., Greek philosopher. * * * ▪ Greek philosopher born 214?, BC died 129?       Greek philosopher who headed the New Academy at Athens when antidogmatic Skepticism reached its greatest strength.       A native… …   Universalium

  • Carneades — (c. 214–129 BC) The most prominent member of the later Academy after Arcesilaus . Carneades was a distinguished sceptic, famous (especially through the report by Cicero ) for impressive speeches at Rome on two successive days in either 155 or 156 …   Philosophy dictionary

  • CARNEADES — I. CARNEADES Cyrenaeus, novae seu tertiae Academiae princeps, Chrysippi maxime studiosus, de quo Gellius, itemque Plin. l. 25. c. 5. ait, scripturum adversus Zenonis Stoici libros superiora capitis helleborô candidô pur gâsse, ne quid ex… …   Hofmann J. Lexicon universale

  • Carnéades de Cirene — Carnéades (en griego Καρνεάδης ο Κυρηναίος) (n. ca. 214 adC m. ca. 129 adC) filósofo y orador griego. Nació en la colonia griega de Cirene, convirtiéndose más tarde en ciudadano ateniense. Fue director de la Academia desde ca. 160 adC hasta ca.… …   Enciclopedia Universal

  • Carneades — See Sceptics ( …   History of philosophy

  • Carnéades — (Karneádēs) ► (214 129 a C) Filósofo griego de Cirene. Dirigió sus teorías contra los epicúreos y los estoicos …   Enciclopedia Universal

  • CARNEADES —    a Greek philosopher, born at Cyrene; his whole philosophy a polemic against the dogmatism of the Stoics, on the alleged ground of the absence of any criterion of certainty in matters of either science or morality; conceded that truth and… …   The Nuttall Encyclopaedia

  • Carneades — /kahr nee euh deez /, n. 214? 129? B.C., Greek philosopher …   Useful english dictionary

  • Plank of Carneades — In ethics, the plank of Carneades is a thought experiment first proposed by Carneades of Cyrene; it explores the concept of self defense in relation to murder.In the thought experiment, there are two shipwrecked sailors, A and B. They both see a… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”