Turing reduction

Turing reduction

In computability theory, a Turing reduction from a problem A to a problem B, named after Alan Turing, is a reduction which solves A, assuming B is already known (Rogers 1967, Soare 1987). It can be understood as an algorithm that could be used to solve A if it had available to it a subroutine for solving B. More formally, a Turing reduction is a function computable by an oracle machine with an oracle for B. Turing reductions can be applied to both decision problems and function problems.

If a Turing reduction of A to B exists then every algorithm for B can be used to produce an algorithm for A, by inserting the algorithm for B at each place where the oracle machine computing A queries the oracle for B. However, because the oracle machine may query the oracle a large number of times, the resulting algorithm may require more time asymptotically than either M or the oracle machine, and may require as much space as both together.

The first formal definition of relative computability, then called relative reducibility, was given by Alan Turing in 1939 in terms of oracle machines. Later in 1943 and 1952 Stephen Kleene defined an equivalent concept in terms of recursive functions. In 1944 Emil Post used the term "Turing reducibility" to refer to the concept.

Contents

Definition

Given two sets A,B \subseteq \mathbb{N} of natural numbers, we say A is Turing reducible to B and write

A \leq_T B

if there is an oracle machine that computes the characteristic function of A when run with oracle B. In this case, we also say A is B-recursive and B-computable.

If there is an oracle machine that, when run with oracle B, computes a partial function with domain A, then A is said to be B-recursively enumerable and B-computably enumerable.

We say A is Turing equivalent to B and write A \equiv_T B\, if both A \leq_T B and B \leq_T A. The equivalence classes of Turing equivalent sets are called Turing degrees. The Turing degree of a set X is written \textbf{deg}(X).

Given a set \mathcal{X} \subseteq \mathcal{P}(\mathbb{N}), a set A \subseteq \mathbb{N} is called Turing hard for \mathcal{X} if X \leq_T A for all X \in \mathcal{X}. If additionally A \in \mathcal{X} then A is called Turing complete for \mathcal{X}.

Relation of Turing completeness to computational universality

Turing completeness, as just defined above, corresponds only partially to Turing completeness in the sense of computational universality. Specifically, a Turing machine is a universal Turing machine if its halting problem (i.e., the set of inputs for which it eventually halts) is many-one complete. Thus, a necessary but insufficient condition for a machine to be computationally universal, is that the machine's halting problem be Turing-complete for the set \mathcal{X} of recursively enumerable sets.

Example

Let We denote the set of input values for which the Turing machine with index e halts. Then the sets A = \{e \mid e \in W_e\} and B = \{(e,n) \mid n \in W_e \} are Turing equivalent (here (e,n) denotes an effective pairing function). A reduction showing A \leq_T B can be constructed using the fact that e \in A \Leftrightarrow (e,e) \in B. Given a pair (e,n), a new index i(e,n) can be constructed using the smn theorem such that the program coded by i(e,n) ignores its input and merely simulates the computation of the machine with index e on input n. In particular, the machine with index i(e,n) either halts on every input or halts on no input. Thus i(e,n) \in A \Leftrightarrow (e,n) \in B holds for all e and n. Because the function i is computable, this shows B \leq_T A. The reductions presented here are not only Turing reductions but many-one reductions, discussed below.

Properties

  • Every set is Turing equivalent to its complement
  • Every computable set is Turing reducible to every other computable set. Because these sets can be computed with no oracle, they can be computed by an oracle machine that ignores the oracle it is given.
  • The relation \leq_T is transitive: if A \leq_T B and B \leq_T C then A \leq_T C. Moreover A \leq A holds for every set A, and thus the relation \leq_T is a preorder (it is not a partial order because A \leq_T B and B \leq_T A does not necessarily imply A = B).
  • There are pairs of sets (A,B) such that A is not Turing reducible to B and B is not Turing reducible to A. Thus \leq_T is not a linear order.
  • There are infinite decreasing sequences of sets under \leq_T. Thus this relation is not well-founded.
  • Every set is Turing reducible to its own Turing jump, but the Turing jump of a set is never Turing reducible to the original set.

The use of a reduction

Since every reduction from a set B to a set A has to determine whether a single element is in A in only finitely many steps, it can only make finitely many queries of membership in the set B. When the amount of information about the set B used to compute a single bit of A is discussed, this is made precise by the use function. Formally, the use of a reduction is the function that sends each natural number n to the largest natural number m whose membership in the set B was queried by the reduction while determining the membership of n in A.

Stronger reductions

There are two common ways of producing reductions stronger than Turing reducibility. The first way is to limit the number and manner of oracle queries.

  • A set A is many-one reducible to B if there is a total computable function f such that an element n is in A if and only if f(n) is in B. Such a function can be used to generate a Turing reduction (by computing f(n), querying the oracle, and then interpreting the result).
  • A truth table reduction or a weak truth table reduction must present all of its oracle queries at the same time. In a truth table reduction, the reduction also gives a boolean function (a truth table) which, when given the answers to the queries, will produce the final answer of the reduction. In a weak truth table reduction, the reduction uses the oracle answers as a basis for further computation depending on the given answers (but not using the oracle). Equivalently, a weak truth table reduction is one for which the use of the reduction is bounded by a computable function. For this reason, weak truth table reductions are sometimes called "bounded Turing" reductions.

The second way to produce a stronger reducibility notion is to limit the computational resources that the program implementing the Turing reduction may use. These limits on the computational complexity of the reduction are important when studying subrecursive classes such as P. A set A is polynomial-time reducible to a set B if there is a Turing reduction of A to B that runs in polynomial time. The concept of log-space reduction is similar.

Note that while these reductions are stronger in the sense that they provide a finer distinction into equivalence classes, and have more restrictive requirements than Turing reductions, this is because the reductions themselves are less powerful; there may be no way to build a many-one reduction from one set to another even when a Turing reduction for the same sets exists.

Weaker reductions

According to the Church-Turing thesis, a Turing reduction is the most general form of an effectively calculable reduction. Nevertheless, weaker reductions are also considered. A set A is said to be arithmetical in B if A is definable by a formula of Peano arithmetic with B as a parameter. The set A is hyperarithmetical in B if there is a recursive ordinal α such that A is computable from B(α), the α-iterated Turing jump of B. The notion of relative constructibility is an important reducibility notion in set theory.

References

  • M. Davis, ed., 1965. The Undecidable—Basic Papers on Undecidable Propositions, Unsolvable Problems and Computable Functions, Raven, New York. Reprint, Dover, 2004. ISBN 0-486-43228-9.
  • S. C. Kleene, 1952. Introduction to Metamathematics. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
  • S. C. Kleene and E. L. Post, 1954. "The upper semi-lattice of degrees of recursive unsolvability". Annals of Mathematics v. 2 n. 59, 379—407.
  • E. Post, 1944. "Recursively enumerable sets of positive integers and their decision problems." Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, v. 50, pp. 284-316. Reprinted in "The Undecidable", M. Davis ed., 1965.
  • A. Turing, 1939. "Systems of logic based on ordinals." Proceedings of the London Mathematics Society, ser. 2 v. 45, pp. 161–228. Reprinted in "The Undecidable", M. Davis ed., 1965.
  • H. Rogers, 1967. Theory of recursive functions and effective computability. McGraw-Hill.
  • R. Soare, 1987. Recursively enumerable sets and degrees, Springer.
  • Davis, Martin (November 2006). "What is...Turing Reducibility?" (PDF). Notices of the American Mathematical Society 53 (10): pp.1218–1219. http://www.ams.org/notices/200610/whatis-davis.pdf. Retrieved 2008-01-16. 

External links


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем решить контрольную работу

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Reduction (complexity) — Example of a reduction from a boolean satisfiability problem to a vertex cover problem. Blue vertices form a vertex cover which corresponds to truth values. In computability theory and computational complexity theory, a reduction is a… …   Wikipedia

  • Reduction (recursion theory) — In computability theory, many reducibility relations (also called reductions, reducibilities, and notions of reducibility) are studied. They are motivated by the question: given sets A and B of natural numbers, is it possible to effectively… …   Wikipedia

  • Turing completeness — For the usage of this term in the theory of relative computability by oracle machines, see Turing reduction. In computability theory, a system of data manipulation rules (such as an instruction set, a programming language, or a cellular… …   Wikipedia

  • Turing degree — Post s problem redirects here. For the other Post s problem , see Post s correspondence problem. In computer science and mathematical logic the Turing degree or degree of unsolvability of a set of natural numbers measures the level of algorithmic …   Wikipedia

  • Turing's proof — First published in January 1937 with the title On Computable Numbers, With an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem , Turing s proof was the second proof of the assertion (Alonzo Church proof was first) that some questions are undecidable :… …   Wikipedia

  • Truth table reduction — In computability theory, a truth table reduction is a reduction from one set of natural numbers to another. Truth table reductions are less powerful than Turing reductions, since not every Turing reduction between sets can be performed by a truth …   Wikipedia

  • Log-space reduction — In computational complexity theory, a log space reduction is a reduction computable by a deterministic Turing machine using logarithmic space. Conceptually, this means it can keep a constant number of pointers into the input, along with a… …   Wikipedia

  • Polynomial-time reduction — In computational complexity theory a polynomial time reduction is a reduction which is computable by a deterministic Turing machine in polynomial time. If it is a many one reduction, it is called a polynomial time many one reduction, polynomial… …   Wikipedia

  • Post–Turing machine — The article Turing machine gives a general introduction to Turing machines, while this article covers a specific class of Turing machines. A Post–Turing machine is a program formulation of an especially simple type of Turing machine, comprising a …   Wikipedia

  • Many-one reduction — In computability theory and computational complexity theory, a many one reduction is a reduction which converts instances of one decision problem into instances of a second decision problem. Reductions are thus used to measure the relative… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”