Gaunilo of Marmoutiers

Gaunilo of Marmoutiers

Gaunilo (or Gaunilon) of Marmoutiers was an 11th-century Benedictine monk, best known for his criticism of St Anselm's ontological argument for the existence of God. His thesis "On Behalf of the Fool" takes its name from the fools mentioned in Psalms 14:1 and Psalms 53:1, who say in their hearts that there is no God. Anselm referred to them in developing his ontological argument in the "Proslogion". Little beyond this essay is known of Gaunilo; no other extant writings bear his name.

The "Lost Island" refutation

Anselm claimed his ontological argument as proof of the existence of God, whom he described as that being than which no greater can be conceived. A god that does not exist cannot be that than which no greater can be conceived, as existence would make it greater. Thus, according to St. Anselm, the concept of God necessarily entails His existence.

Gaunilo criticised Anselm's argument by employing the same reasoning, via "reductio ad absurdum", to "prove" the existence of the mythical "Lost Island", the greatest or most perfect island conceivable: if the island of which we are thinking does not exist, it cannot be the greatest conceivable island, for, to be the greatest conceivable island, it would have to exist, as any existent island would be greater than an imaginary one. This, of course, is merely a direct application of Anselm's own premise that existence is a perfection. Since we can conceive of this greatest or most perfect conceivable island, it must, by Anselm's way of thinking, exist. While this argument is absurd, Gaunilo claims that it is no more so than Anselm's.

Philosophers often attempt to prove the ontological argument wrong by comparing Anselm's with Gaunilo's. The former runs thus:

# God is that being than which no greater can be conceived.
# It is greater to exist in reality than merely as an idea.
# If God does not exist, we can conceive of an even greater being, "id est" one that "does" exist.
# Therefore, God must indeed exist in reality.
# Therefore, He exists.

Gaunilo's argument runs along the same lines:

# The Lost Island is that than which no greater can be conceived.
# It is greater to exist in reality than merely as an idea.
# If the Lost Island does not exist, one can conceive of an even greater island, "id est" one that does exist.
# Therefore, the Lost Island exists in reality.

If one of these arguments is sound, it has been asserted, they must both be sound. By Gaunilo's reckoning, however, one (and, therefore, the other, too) is unsound. The Lost Island does not exist, so there is something wrong with the logic that proves that it does. Because the argument proves true in one case that which is patently false (the Lost Island), it is fair to ask whether it may fairly be regarded as proving true the other case. The fact that there is no perfect island is believed to show that the logic of the ontological argument for God's existence is flawed.

Such objections are called overload objections: they do not claim to show where or how the argument goes wrong; they merely argue that, if it is sound in one application, it is unsound in all others. Simply put, they are arguments that would overload the world with an indefinitely large number of things, like perfect islands.

Criticisms

Gaunilo's objection to the ontological argument has been criticised on several grounds. One concerns the very idea of a perfect island, which, presumably, has an abundance of lush trees and pristine beaches. The more of these that an island has, it is held, the better the island is.

But there is no intrinsically maximum number of trees or beaches that an island could possibly have: for any one conceivable island, there is another, even greater, with one more palm tree and one more beach. Ergo, there is no island than which no greater can be conceived. The concept of the perfect island is incoherent: there is and can be no such thing.

Alvin Plantinga tendered a reply to Gaunilo's remonstrance by arguing that the concept of "that than which nothing greater can be conceived" is not applicable to an island, or any other object, in the way that it is applicable to God. Plantinga defends Anselm's proof by averring that it applies exclusively to Him, a viewpoint that Anselm himself had stated but failed to elucidate. A necessary being is both existent and the greatest conceivable and greatest possible being. Only God, as he is defined, meets all of those criteria and can, therefore, be dubbed a necessary being.

Another criticism of Gaunilo's argument points out that, whereas God is that "thing" than which no greater can be conceived, Gaunilo's is merely that "island" than which no greater can be conceived. Thus, while no island may exceed it in greatness, it is perfectly reasonable to suppose that some non-island could. "Consequently," wrote William L. Rowe in his summary of the polemic, "if we follow Anselm's reasoning exactly, it does not appear that we can derive an absurdity from the supposition that the island than which none greater is possible does not exist." [Rowe: "The Ontological Argument" in Feinberg; Shafer-Landau: "Reason & Responsibility", p. 15.]

Gaunilo's criticisms of St Anselm's version of the ontological argument may be seen to be unsuccessful in ruling out the ontological argument as proof of the existence of God, but they do succeed in raising doubt about the logical structure of Anselm's proof.

Bibliography

*Feinberg, Joel; Shafer-Landau, Russ: "Reason & Responsibility: Readings in Some Basic Problems of Philosophy: Thirteenth Edition" (Thomson Wadsworth, 2008).

Notes


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Gaunilo — (eleventh century)    Theologian.    Gaunilo was a Benedictine monk of the community of Marmoutiers, France. He criticised anselm’s ontological argument for the existence of God (as expressed in his Proslogion), by taking on the guise of the fool …   Who’s Who in Christianity

  • Ontological argument — The ontological argument for the existence of God (or simply ontological argument) is an a priori proof for the existence of God. The ontological argument was first proposed by the eleventh century monk Anselm of Canterbury, who defined God as… …   Wikipedia

  • Proslogion — Das Proslogion ist ein von Anselm von Canterbury in der Frühscholastik 1077/78 verfasstes Werk. Es gilt als das erste Werk, das einen ontologischen Gottesbeweis enthält, und erlangte deshalb größere philosophiegeschichtliche Bedeutung.… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Argumento ontológico — Saltar a navegación, búsqueda El argumento ontológico para la existencia de Dios es un razonamiento apriorístico que pretende probar la existencia de Dios empleando únicamente la razón y la intuición. Dentro del contexto de las religiones… …   Wikipedia Español

  • Agnosticism — Certainty series Agnosticism Belief Certainty Doubt Determinism Epistemology Estimation Fallibilism …   Wikipedia

  • Afterlife — For other uses, see Afterlife (disambiguation). After death , Life after death , and Hereafter redirect here. For other uses, see After death (disambiguation), Life after death (disambiguation), and Hereafter (disambiguation). Ancient Egyptian… …   Wikipedia

  • Animism — (from Latin anima soul, life )[1][2] refers to the belief that non human entities are spiritual beings, or at least embody some kind of life principle.[3] Animism encompasses the beliefs that there is no separation between the spiritual and… …   Wikipedia

  • Argument from morality — The argument from morality is one of many arguments for the existence of God. It comes in different forms, all aiming to support the claim that God exists with observations about morality. Its counterpoint is generally the Problem of evil.… …   Wikipedia

  • Augustine of Hippo — This article is about the theologian and philosopher, Augustine of Hippo. For his theodicy regarding the problem of evil, see Augustinian theodicy. Augustine , Saint Augustine , and Augustinus redirect here. For other uses, see Augustine… …   Wikipedia

  • Cosmological argument — The cosmological argument is an argument for the existence of a First Cause (or instead, an Uncaused cause) to the universe, and by extension is often used as an argument for the existence of an unconditioned or supreme being, usually then… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”