Categories (Aristotle)

Categories (Aristotle)

Categories (Lat. "Categoriae", Greek "Κατηγορίαι" "Katēgoriai") is a text from Aristotle's Organon that enumerates all the possible kinds of thing which can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition.

The "Categories" places every object of human apprehension under one of ten categories (known to medieval writers as the "praedicamenta"). They are intended to enumerate everything which can be expressed without composition or structure, thus anything which can be either the subject or the predicate of a proposition.

The text begins with an explication of what is meant by "synonymous," or univocal words, what is meant by "homonymous," or equivocal words, and what is meant by "paronymous," or denominative words. It then divides forms of speech as being:
* Either simple, without composition or structure, such as "man," "horse," "fights," etc.
* Or having composition and structure, such as "a man fights," "the horse runs," etc.

Next, we distinguish between a subject of "predication", namely that of which anything is affirmed or denied, and a subject of "inhesion". A thing is said to be inherent in a subject, when, though it is not a part of the subject, it cannot possibly exist without the subject, e.g., shape in a thing having a shape.

Of all the things that exist,
# Some may be predicated of a subject, but are in no subject; as "man" may be predicated of James or John, but is not in any subject.
# Some are in a subject, but can be predicated of no subject. Thus my knowledge in grammar is in me as its subject, but it can be predicated of no subject; because it is an individual thing.
# Some are both in a subject, and may be predicated of a subject, as science, which is in the mind as its subject, and may be predicated of geometry.
# Last, some things can neither be in a subject nor be predicated of any subject. These are "individual substances", which cannot be predicated, because they are individuals; and cannot be in a subject, because they are substances.

Then we come to the categories themselves, (1)-(4) above being called by the scholastics the "antepraedicamenta". Note, however, that although Aristotle has apparently distinguished between being in a subject, and being predicated truly of a subject, in the "Prior Analytics" these are treated as synonymous. This has led some to suspect that Aristotle was not the author of the "Categories".

The ten categories, or classes, are
# Substance. As mentioned above, the notion of "substance" is defined as that which can be said to be predicated of nothing nor be said to be within anything. Hence, "this particular man" or "that particular tree" are substances. Later in the text, Aristotle calls these particulars "primary substances," to distinguish them from "secondary substances," which are universals. Hence, "Socrates" is a primary Substance, while "man" is a secondary substance.
# Quantity. This is the extension of an object, and may be either or . Further, its parts may or may not have relative positions to each other. All medieval discussions about the nature of the continuum, of the infinite and the infinitely divisible, are a long footnote to this text. It is of great importance in the development of mathematical ideas in the medieval and late scholastic period.
# Quality This is a determination which characterizes the nature of an object.
# Relation This is the way in which one object may be related to another.
# Place Position in relation to the surrounding environment.
# Time Position in relation to the course of events.
# Position The examples Aristotle gives indicate that he meant a condition of rest resulting from an action: "‘Lying’, ‘sitting’." Thus "position" may be taken as the end point for the corresponding action. The term is, however, frequently taken to mean the relative position of the parts of an object (usually a living object), given that the position of the parts is inseparable from the state of rest implied.
# State The examples Aristotle gives indicate that he meant a condition of rest resulting from an affection (i.e. being acted on): "‘shod’, ‘armed’." The term is, however, frequently taken to mean the determination arising from the physical accoutrements of an object: one's shoes, one's arms, etc. Traditionally, this category is also called a "habitus" (from Latin "habere" "to have").
# Action The production of change in some other object.
# Affection The reception of change from some other object. It is also known as "passivity." It is clear from the examples Aristotle gave for action and for affection that action is to affection as the active voice is to the passive. Thus for action he gave the example, "‘to lance’, ‘to cauterize’;" for affection, "‘to be lanced’, ‘to be cauterized.’" The term is frequently misinterpreted to mean a kind of emotion or passion.

The first six are given a detailed treatment in four chapters, the last four are passed over lightly, as being clear in themselves. Later texts by scholastic philosophers also reflect this disparity of treatment.

After discussing the categories, four ways are given in which things may be considered "contrary" to one another. Next, the work discusses five senses wherein a thing may be considered "prior" to another, followed by a short section on simultaneity. Six forms of movement are then defined: generation, destruction, increase, diminution, alteration, and change of place. The work ends with a brief consideration of the word 'have' and its usage.

External links

*" [http://www.classicallibrary.org/aristotle/categories/index.htm Categories] ", translated by E. M. Edghill
*" [http://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/520/Cats1-5.pdf Categories] " ch. 1-5, translated by J. L. Ackrill (.pdf file)
*" [http://www.formalontology.it/aristotle-categories.htm Aristotle's Theory of Categories] " with an extensive bibliography
*sep entry|aristotle-categories|Aristotle's Categories|Paul Studtmann

ee also

* Category (philosophy)
* Categorization
* Category (Kant)
* Schema (Kant)
* Categories (Stoic)
* Category
* Simplicius of Cilicia


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно сделать НИР?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Aristotle’s logic and metaphysics — Alan Code PART 1: LOGICAL WORKS OVERVIEW OF ARISTOTLE’S LOGIC The Aristotelian logical works are referred to collectively using the Greek term ‘Organon’. This is a reflection of the idea that logic is a tool or instrument of, though not… …   History of philosophy

  • Aristotle — • Philosopher, born at Stagira, a Grecian colony in the Thracian peninsula Chalcidice, 384 B.C.; died at Chalcis, in Euboea, 322 B.C Catholic Encyclopedia. Kevin Knight. 2006. Aristotle     Aristotle …   Catholic encyclopedia

  • CATEGORIES — CATEGORIES, in medieval Jewish philosophy the highest logical as well as metaphysical classification into which all beings are divided. aristotle (Categories, chs. 5–9; Metaphysics, book 5, especially chs. 8 and 30. speaks of the categories which …   Encyclopedia of Judaism

  • Aristotle — /ar euh stot l/, n. 384 322 B.C., Greek philosopher: pupil of Plato; tutor of Alexander the Great. * * * born 384, Stagira died 322 BC, Chalcis Greek philosopher and scientist whose thought determined the course of Western intellectual history… …   Universalium

  • Aristotle the philosopher of nature — David Furley 1 THE TREATISES ON NATURE The subject matter of the present chapter is what Aristotle has to say about the natural world the subject that in classical Greek is most accurately rendered as ta physika. But of course this includes many… …   History of philosophy

  • Aristotle Onassis — Aristotle Socrates Onassis Born 15 January 1906(1906 01 15) Smyrna, Ottoman Empire Died 15 March 1975(1975 03 15) (aged 69) …   Wikipedia

  • Categories — Catégories Pour les articles homonymes, voir Catégorie. Les Catégories est une œuvre attribuée à Aristote qui a été placée en tête de l Organon. Plusieurs raisons en apparence solides, tirées d indices à la fois internes et externes, militent… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Catégories — Pour les articles homonymes, voir Catégorie. Les Catégories est une œuvre attribuée à Aristote qui a été placée en tête de l Organon. Plusieurs raisons en apparence solides, tirées d indices à la fois internes et externes, militent contre l… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Aristotle — For other uses, see Aristotle (disambiguation). Ἀριστοτέλης, Aristotélēs Marble bust of Aristotle. Roman copy after a Gree …   Wikipedia

  • Categories (Stoic) — The term Stoic Categories refers to Stoic ideas regarding Categories: the most fundamental classes of being for all things. The Stoics believed there were four categories (substance, quality, disposition, relative dispostion) which were the… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”