Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)

Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)

The theory of Potentiality and Actuality is one of the central themes of Aristotle's philosophy and metaphysics. With these two notions, Aristotle intends to provide a structure for the comprehension of reality. Potency refers, generally, to the capacity or power of a virtual reality to come to be in actuality. In broad terms, potency is a capacity, and actuality is its fulfillment.

Senses of being

"Being", according to Aristotle, has many senses. As being can be studied by many sciences in many different aspects, there are different senses in which being can be understood (indeed, if we do not take into account these multiple aspects, philosophy may lose some of its universal scope). In numerous passages of his Metaphysics1, Aristotle makes the following divisions:

* Being as "per accidens" ("katà symbebekós") and being as "per se" ("kath' autó").
* Being as substance or accident.
* Being true and being as false.
* Being as potency ("dýnamis") and act ("enérgeia" or "enteléxeia").

The first distinction deals with being as an unnecessary coincidence: for example, John being a "musician" and also being "tall". It is not necessary for a tall man to be a musician, or viceversa. Thus, Aristotle explains2, something is said to be "per accidens" when two realities are found within a subject, and it is not necessary for them to be so. Being as true and false corresponds to the relation between what is thought and what is real. If I believe a white wall to be red, my belief does not correspond to reality, and so it is false. For Aristotle, this a peculiar kind of non-being. Being as a substance refers to being as the ultimate subject of predication. Accidents are always predicated of a substance ("musician" and "tall", for example, are predicates of John). Thus, accidents depend on a substance for their existence.Potency and act, lastly, are said of Aristotles to be a fourth group of concepts that help us understand being but, unlike the other three, these concepts are said of the whole other three groups (V, 7, Bk 1017a). Potentiality refers to beings that are not yet come to be; actuality refers to beings that have come to be and are "now" (actually) being.

Potency and actuality as a real distinction

Aristotle argues against those who claim that potency is only a mental concept (that is, not a "real" sense of being). In "Metaphysics" IX, 3-4, he argues against Megarics, who claimed that potency could only be had by a subject when the subject was actually performing a specific action. Aristotle claims this is not logical, because then one would only possess a potency when one was excerting its corresponding act. A man who is sitting, for example, would not "have" the potency to stand. He would only have the potency of standing while actually standing. Aristotle believes this to be paradoxical. He, therefore, believes:
# That potency is a real sense of being3.
# That potency is always ordained to an act.

Act is, therefore, the primal sense. Potency is always said in reference to it. Accordingly, the different senses of act, which Aristotle also recognizes, must correspond to different senses of potency.

enses of act

According to Aristotle, there are three great senses of act: movement ("kinesis"), form, and knowledge. Other senses, like nature ("phusis"), habit ("hexis"), etc., may be reduced to these three. Movement is defined by Aristotle in his book on Physics as "The fulfillment of what exists potentially, insofar as it exists potentially, is motion"5. This is known as a "transitive" act. Transitivity is the expression of an act in which something changes for something else. Movement can therefore be understood under the more general term of "metabolé", that is, change. The corresponding potency is, thus, a transitiv potency, or kinetic potency.

Now, substance is a formal act. Moreover, a formal act is always the end of a transitive movement. Substance can also then be understood as "metabolé". Indeed, as Aristotle explains movement, it always implies: a cause from which it takes place, a subject in which it takes place, and a form (end, péras) it which knowledge takes place6. In all these cases, movement is always found within the categories (the second sense of being mentioned above) and is always a causal act7.

To these two senses of act corresponds what Aristotle calls "transitive potency", or simply potency. This kind of potency is described in "Metaphysics" V, 12 and IX, 1-5. The two passages are similar and, in the end, Aristotle reaches a general notion of potency: a principle of movement, that is, the capacity of something to move something. The mover (which is called active potency) moves what is moved (called passive potency). Their union constitutes an act: both are different potencies that join in one and the same act8.

The central characteristic of both these potencies (and acts) is that, when acquiring a new form, the old form is lost. When painting a blue wall white, the form "blue" is lost just as the form "white" is acquired. That is the concept of "transitivity".

There is, however, a different sense of act, that in a way "transcends" categories. This act is knowledge, or "energeia". Aristotle describes it in order to show the difference it has with movement and form:

Since no action which has a limit is an end, but only a means to the end, as, e.g., the process of thinning; and since the parts of the body themselves, when one is thinning them, are in motion in the sense that they are not already that which it is the object of the motion to make them, this process is not an action, or at least not a complete one, since it is not an end; it is the process which includes the end that is an action. E.g., at the same time we see and have seen, understand and have understood, think and have thought; but we cannot at the same time learn and have learnt, or become healthy and be healthy. We are living well and have lived well, we are happy and have been happy, at the same time; otherwise the process would have had to cease at some time, like the thinning-process; but it has not ceased at the present moment; we both are living and have lived.
Now of these processes we should call the one type motions, and the other actualizations. Every motion is incomplete--the processes of thinning, learning, walking, building--these are motions, and incomplete at that. For it is not the same thing which at the same time is walking and has walked, or is building and has built, or is becoming and has become, or is being moved and has been moved, but two different things; and that which is causing motion is different from that which has caused motion. But the same thing at the same time is seeing and has seen, is thinking and has thought. The latter kind of process, then, is what I mean by actualization, and the former what I mean by motion9.

In the "Metaphysics" Aristotle gives extraordinary examples: we see and we have seen, we think and have thought; but we don’t build and have built. Building is a transitive action, an imperfect action. In the perfect action, praxis, the object (the end of the action) is immediately possessed, at the same time, simultaneously. Knowledge is not a change of a form, a change of quality, because a form is not corrupted by the acquisition of a new one; rather, both forms co-exist in one act10. That is why knowledge is not only the possession of a form: it is the possession of another being’s form. And not only that: knowledge is the possession of another’s form as another’s form. When knowing a stone, we do not become the stone, even as we do have its form as one in act with the act of knowledge. Movement does not possess its object. Movement does not exist at once with its object, for possessing the object would mean the end of movement. Movement is not co-actual with its end, as knowledge is11.

Potency and possibility

According to what we have said, if knowledge is not a transitive action, its correspondent potency should also be intransitive. Indeed, it is possible in some texts to find an account of possibility which suggests that Aristotle has in mind a different form of potency. However, the texts are not clear enough, and many interpretations have been given to them. One could, for example, read the following passages: "Metaphysics" IX, 3, Bk 1047a 24;IX, 6, Bk 1048a 28-30; "De Interpretatione" 23a 8-16. In this last text Aristotle states that this potency corresponds not only to mobile being, but also to eternal beings (that is, beings outside the range of "kinesis").

What follows is only a possible way of accounting for the different meanings of "potency" in Aristotle. The distinction is made according to the Greek terms:

# Potency in the order of reality: "dynatón".
#* dynatòn katà dýnamin: everything that is possible;
#* ón dynámei: the being that simply has a potency (which can be active or passive);
#* dynatòn katà tò télos: the same real potency according to its goal.
# Potency in the logical order: "dynatà oú katà dýnamin".

Later, the notion of possibility will be greatly analyzed by modern philosophers. Indeed, many philosophical interpretations of possibility are related to a famous passage on Aristotle's "On Interpretation", concerning the truth of the statement: "There will be a sea battle tomorrow"12.
Current versions of the notion of possibility are studied by Modal Metaphysics and Modal Logic.
Some philosophers claim that "actuality" refers to the act of knowledge (the third sense of act); the transitive act would not be an actuality but, rather, an "activity".

Notes

1 For example: "Metaphysics" V, 7; VI, 2, etc.
2 "Metaphysics" V, 7, Bk 1017a 19 ff. (Normally, Bekker numbers are used to identify passages in Aristotle's texts. This system was established by August Immanuel Bekker's edition of Aristotle.)
3 Some illuminating passages: "Physics" III, 1, Bk 201a 10; III, 6, Bk 206a 14; "Metaphysics" VI, 2, Bk 1026b 1; 1071a 18s; IX, 3, 1047a 18-20, etc.
4 Aristotle uses many different words and notions that signify different aspects of the formal act. For example: "tode ti", "to ti en einai", "eidos", "morphe", "ti esti", "sxema", etc. Normally, "morphe" is understood as the generic name of the form; if a particular "morphe" is the one that most determines a substance ("ousía"), it may be understood as "essence" ("tode ti", "to ti en einai"). The word "eidos" seems to refer to the intellectual apprehension of the form. The term is taken from Plato's "forms" ("eide").
5See "Physics" III, 1, Bk 201a 6. And further on he writes: "Examples will elucidate this definition of motion. When the buildable, insofar as it is just that, is fully real, it is being built, and this is building". Clearly, a building that is being built is not a complete building. A complete (actual) building is one that does not need to be built. But knowledge is different: we see, writes Aristotle, and we have seen, and we keep seeing.
6 See "Physics" V, 1, Bk 224a 34ff.
7 See "Physics" III, 1, Bk 200b 26ff, and "Metaphysics" XI, 6, Bk 1063a 17ff.
8 See "Metaphysics" IX, 1, 1046a 15-19.
9 This is Hugh Tredennik's edition.
10 See "De anima" II, 5, Bk 417b 14ff.
11 See "Metaphysics" XI, 5, Bk 1065b 34ff.
12 See "On Interpretation" Bk 17a 2.


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем решить контрольную работу

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Potentiality and actuality — Energeia redirects here. For other uses, see Energia (disambiguation) and Energy (disambiguation). Dunamis redirects here. For other uses, see Dunamis (disambiguation). Part of a series on …   Wikipedia

  • Actuality — may refer to: * Modal logic * Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle) * A slogan on the television network TruTV …   Wikipedia

  • Aristotle — For other uses, see Aristotle (disambiguation). Ἀριστοτέλης, Aristotélēs Marble bust of Aristotle. Roman copy after a Gree …   Wikipedia

  • Aristotle the philosopher of nature — David Furley 1 THE TREATISES ON NATURE The subject matter of the present chapter is what Aristotle has to say about the natural world the subject that in classical Greek is most accurately rendered as ta physika. But of course this includes many… …   History of philosophy

  • Aristotle — • Philosopher, born at Stagira, a Grecian colony in the Thracian peninsula Chalcidice, 384 B.C.; died at Chalcis, in Euboea, 322 B.C Catholic Encyclopedia. Kevin Knight. 2006. Aristotle     Aristotle …   Catholic encyclopedia

  • Aristotle’s logic and metaphysics — Alan Code PART 1: LOGICAL WORKS OVERVIEW OF ARISTOTLE’S LOGIC The Aristotelian logical works are referred to collectively using the Greek term ‘Organon’. This is a reflection of the idea that logic is a tool or instrument of, though not… …   History of philosophy

  • Aristotle: Aesthetics and philosophy of mind — David Gallop AESTHETICS Aesthetics, as that field is now understood, does not form the subjectmatter of any single Aristotelian work. No treatise is devoted to such topics as the essential nature of a work of art, the function of art in general,… …   History of philosophy

  • Aristotle — /ar euh stot l/, n. 384 322 B.C., Greek philosopher: pupil of Plato; tutor of Alexander the Great. * * * born 384, Stagira died 322 BC, Chalcis Greek philosopher and scientist whose thought determined the course of Western intellectual history… …   Universalium

  • Metaphysics (Aristotle) — Part of a series on Aristotelianism …   Wikipedia

  • Physics (Aristotle) — Physics (or Physica , or Physicae Auscultationes meaning lessons ) is a key text in the philosophy of Aristotle. It inaugurates the current Andronichean order, the long series of Aristotle s physical, cosmological and biological works, and is… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”