Transposition (logic)

Transposition (logic)

In the methods of deductive reasoning in classical logic, "transposition is the rule of inference that permits one to infer from the truth of "A implies B" the truth of "Not-B implies not-A", and conversely". [Brody, Bobuch A. "Glossary of Logical Terms". "Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Vol. 5-6, p. 76. Macmillan, 1973.] Its symbolic expression is:

: (P → Q) ↔ (~Q → ~P) [Copi, Irving M. "Symbolic Logic". 5th ed. Macmillan, 1979. See the Rules of Replacement, pp. 39-40.]

The "→" is the symbol for material implication and the doubleheaded arrow "↔" indicates a biconditional relationship. The symbol "~" indicates negation. "P" and "Q" are components representing statements that form a truth functional compound proposition, where in a hypothetic proposition the first statement will be the antecedent and the last statement will be the consequent. The expression "truth function" has distinctive applications in philosophical logic and mathematical logic. This article concerns its philosophical application. (See also Transposition (mathematics))

Traditional logic

Form of transposition

In the inferred proposition, the consequent is the contradictory of the antecedent in the original proposition, and the antecedent of the inferred proposition is the contradictory of the consequent of the original proposition. The symbol for material implication signifies the proposition as a hypothetical, or the "if-then" form, e.g. "if P then Q".

The biconditional statement of the rule of transposition (↔) refers to the relation between hypothetical (→) "propositions", with each proposition including an antecent and consequential term. As a matter of logical inference, to transpose, or convert the terms of one proposition requires the conversion of the terms of the propositions on both sides of the biconditional relationship. Meaning, to transpose, or convert (P → Q) to (Q → P) requires that the other proposition, (~Q → ~P), be transposed or converted to (~P → ~Q). Otherwise, to convert the terms of one proposition and not the other renders the rule invalid, violating the sufficient condition and necessary condition of the terms of the propositions, where the violation is that the changed proposition commits the fallacy of denying the antecedent or affirming the consequent by means of illicit conversion

The truth of the rule of transposition is dependent upon the relations of sufficient condition and necessary condition in logic.

Sufficient condition

In the proposition "If P then Q", the occurrence of 'P' is sufficient reason for the occurrence of 'Q'. 'P', as an individual or a class, materially implicates 'Q', but the relation of 'Q' to 'P', is such that the converse proposition "If Q then P" does not necessarily have sufficient condition. The rule of inference for sufficient condition is "modus ponens", which is an argument for conditional implication:

Premise (1): If P, then Q

Premise (2): P

Conclusion: Therefore, Q

Necessary condition

Since the converse of premise (1) is not valid, all that can be stated of the relationship of 'P' and 'Q' is that in the absence of 'Q', 'P' does not occur, meaning that 'Q' is the necessary condition for 'P'. The rule of inference for necessary condition is "modus tollens":

Premise (1): If P, then Q

Premise (2): not Q

Conclusion: Therefore, not P

Grammatically speaking

A grammatical example traditionally used by logicians contrasting sufficient and necessary conditions is the statement "If there is fire, then oxygen is present". An oxygenated environment is necessary for fire or combustion, but simply because there is an oxygenated environment does not necessarily mean that fire or combustion is occurring. While one can infer that fire stipulates the presence of oxygen, from the presence of oxygen the converse "If there is oxygen present, then fire is present" cannot be inferred. All that can be inferred from the original proposition is that "If oxygen is not present, then there cannot be fire".

Relationship of propositions

The symbol for the biconditional ("↔") signifies the relationship between the propositions is both necessary and sufficient, and is verbalized as "if and only if", or, according to the example "If P then Q 'if and only if' if not Q then not P".

Necessary and sufficient conditions can be explained by analogy in terms of the concepts and the rules of immediate inference of traditional logic. In the categorical proposition "All S is P", the subject term 'S' is said to be distributed, that is, all members of its class are exhausted in its expression. Conversely, the predicate term 'P' cannot be said to be distributed, or exhausted in its expression because it is indeterminate whether every instance of a member of 'P' as a class is also a member of 'S' as a class. All that can be validly inferred is that "Some P are S". Thus, the type 'A' proposition "All P is S" cannot be inferred by conversion from the original 'A' type proposition "All S is P". All that can be inferred is the type "A" proposition "All non-P is non-S" (Note that (P → Q) and (~Q → ~P) are both 'A' type propositions). Grammatically, one cannot infer "all mortals are men" from "All men are mortal". An 'A' type proposition can only be immediately inferred by conversion when both the subject and predicate are distributed, as in the inference "All bachelors are unmarried men" from "All unmarried men are bachelors".

Transposition and the method of contraposition

In traditional logic the reasoning process of transposition as a rule of inference is applied to categorical propositions through contraposition and obversion, [Stebbing, 1961, p. 65-66. For reference to the initial step of contraposition as obversion and conversion, see Copi, 1953, p. 141.] a series of immediate inferences where the rule of obversion is first applied to the original categorical proposition "All S is P"; yielding the obverse "No S is non-P". In the obversion of the original proposition to an 'E' type proposition, both terms become distributed. The obverse is then converted, resulting in the contrapositive "No non-P is S", maintaining distribution of both terms. The contrapositive is again obverted, resulting in the obverted contrapositive "All non-P is non-S". Since nothing is said in the definition of contraposition with regard to the predicate of the inferred proposition, it is permissible that it could be the original subject or its contradictory, and the predicate term of the resulting 'A' type proposition is again undistributed. This results in two contrapositives, one where the predicate term is distributed, and another where the predicate term is undistributed. [See Stebbing, 1961, pp. 65-66. Also, for reference to the immediate inferences of obversion, conversion, and obversion again, see Copi, 1953, p. 141.]

Differences between transposition and contraposition

Note that the method of transposition and contraposition should not be confused. Contraposition is a type of immediate inference in which from a given categorical proposition another categorical proposition is inferred which has as its subject the contradictory of the original predicate. Since nothing is said in the definition of contraposition with regard to the predicate of the inferred proposition, it is permissible that it could be the original subject or its contradictory. This is in contradistinction to the form of the propositions of transposition, which may be material implication, or a hypothetical statement. The difference is that in its application to categorical propositions the results of contraposition has two contrapositives, each being the obvert of the other, [See Stebbing, 1961, p. 66.] i.e. "No non-P is S" and "All non-P is non-S". The distinction between the two contrapositives is absorbed and eliminated in the principle of transposition, which presupposes the "mediate inferences" [For an explanation of the absorption of obversion and conversion as "mediate inferences see: Copi, Irving. "Symbolic Logic". pp. 171-174, MacMillan, 1979, fifth edition.] of contraposition and is also referred to as the "law of contraposition". [Prior, A.N. "Logic, Traditional". "Encyclopedia of Philosophy", Vol.5, Macmillan, 1973.]

Transposition in mathematical logic

See Transposition (mathematics), Set theory

Bibliography

*Brody, Bobuch A. "Glossary of Logical Terms". Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 5-6, p. 61. Macmillan, 1973.
*Copi, Irving. "Introduction to Logic". MacMillan, 1953.
*Copi, Irving. "Symbolic Logic". MacMillan, 1979, fifth edition.
*Prior, A.N. "Logic, Traditional". "Encyclopedia of Philosophy", Vol.5, Macmillan, 1973.
*Stebbing, Susan. "A Modern Introduction to Logic". Harper, 1961, Seventh edition

Footnotes

ee also

*Contraposition
*Conversion (logic)
*Inference
*Obversion
*Propositional logic
*Syllogism
*Term logic


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем сделать НИР

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Transposition — may mean: * Transposition (cardiac), a congenital heart defect with malformation of any of the major vessels. * Transposition (chess), different moves or a different move order leading to the same position, especially during the openings. *… …   Wikipedia

  • transposition — Term sometimes used in logic for the transformation usually known as contraposition, whereby from (p → q ) we can derive (¬ q → ¬ p ) …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Contraposition (traditional logic) — In traditional logic, contraposition is a form of immediate inference in which from a given proposition another is inferred having for its subject the contradictory of the original predicate, and in some cases involving a change of quality… …   Wikipedia

  • Outline of logic — The following outline is provided as an overview of and topical guide to logic: Logic – formal science of using reason, considered a branch of both philosophy and mathematics. Logic investigates and classifies the structure of statements and… …   Wikipedia

  • Term logic — In philosophy, term logic, also known as traditional logic, is a loose name for the way of doing logic that began with Aristotle, and that was dominant until the advent of modern predicate logic in the late nineteenth century.This entry is an… …   Wikipedia

  • Conversion (logic) — Conversion is a concept in traditional logic referring to a type of immediate inference in which from a given proposition another proposition is inferred which has as its subject the predicate of the original proposition and as its predicate the… …   Wikipedia

  • Converse (logic) — In logic, the converse of a categorical or implicational statement is the result of reversing its two parts. For the implication P → Q, the converse is Q → P. For the categorical proposition All S is P, the converse is All P is S. In neither case …   Wikipedia

  • formal logic — the branch of logic concerned exclusively with the principles of deductive reasoning and with the form rather than the content of propositions. [1855 60] * * * Introduction       the abstract study of propositions, statements, or assertively used …   Universalium

  • Connexive logic — names one class of alternative, or non classical, logics designed to exclude the so called paradoxes of material implication. (Other logical theories with the same agenda include relevance logic, also known as relevant logic.) The characteristic… …   Wikipedia

  • law of transposition — a principle in logic: transposition yields a valid inference …   Useful english dictionary

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”